What I’ve said so far is that there is an important distinction between the requirements of the Constitution and the rules that courts apply to determine whether those requirements have been violated. In the academic literature, recent articles have called the former “operative propositions” and the latter “decision rules.” Here I am calling them “constitutional meaning” and “doctrine” in the hopes that the terminology will be a little more familiar to readers. (Any suggestions for alternatives for the book would be welcome.) And I’ve suggested that keeping this distinction in mind helps us evaluate doctrine and also handle some theoretical problems.
I’m going to start with the theory, because it helps develop the perspective I will bring to the doctrinal analysis. First up is the debate over popular constitutionalism. Popular constitutionalism, championed perhaps most notably in Larry Kramer’s recent book The People Themselves, suggests that the Supreme Court should not be the only interpreter of the Constitution, or even the most important one. The ultimate interpreter of a law, popular constitutionalism suggests, should be the lawgiving sovereign. Hence state courts have the last word on the meaning of state law, and federal courts do with respect to federal law. The Constitution, however, is not ordinary law created by the federal government; it is higher law created by the People, and the People should therefore be the ultimate authority. At the least, popular constitutionalism suggests, the Court should pay some attention to the interpretations of coordinate branches of government, which may tend to be more representative of the People.
The current Supreme Court is notoriously hostile to the idea of popular constitutionalism, and the theme of constitutional interpretation as the Court’s jealously-guarded prerogative runs through a number of recent decisions. Most notably, in its cases dealing with Congress’s power to legislate to enforce the 14th Amendment, the Court has demanded that enforcement legislation track the Court’s practice. Section 5 of the 14th Amendment gives Congress the power to deter or remedy violations of the other sections, the Court says, but a state practice is a violation if and only if the Court would hold it unconstitutional. Congress cannot decide that some practice is unconstitutional and prohibit it on those grounds; it must follow the Court’s lead, because only the Court has the power to decide what the 14th Amendment forbids. Thus, for instance, Congress can legislate to deter or remedy discrimination against people with disabilities under Section 5 only if that discrimination is irrational, because it is only irrational discrimination that the Court will strike down as unconstitutional under Section 1.
Here the dispute between popular constitutionalism and judicial exclusivity is clearly joined: the popular constitutionalists suggest that Congress should be allowed to legislate according to its own interpretation of the 14th Amendment, and the judicial exclusivists (including the
I said last time that the meaning of the Equal Protection Clause was something like “The government may not treat people differently without adequate justification” and that the tiers of scrutiny that have developed as a matter of doctrine were driven by various considerations about when legislatures are superior decisionmakers. A slightly different way of putting this, one that the Supreme Court has used frequently, is that the Equal Protection Clause forbids invidious discrimination—discrimination motivated by hostility or a lack of concern for the welfare of its targets. Assume for the moment that this is what the Court thinks. The next question is what doctrinal rules the Court will adopt to implement the ban on invidious discrimination. In most circumstances, the Court applies rational basis review, which is essentially equivalent to leaving the matter with more representative government actors. In some cases, it applies heightened scrutiny, which reflects the judgment that there are reasons to suspect that the other government actors cannot be trusted. The model of the relationship between doctrine and meaning I develop suggests that rational basis review is doctrine that tends to underenforce constitutional meaning—it will fail to catch some acts of discrimination that are in fact invidious. Heightened scrutiny is doctrine that tends to overenforce constitutional meaning—it will strike down some acts of discrimination that are in fact not invidious.
If this is the case, then Congress in legislating to enforce the Equal Protection clause should be allowed to deter or remedy discrimination against people with disabilities if that discrimination is invidious, not only if it is irrational. This would be so not because Congress has an independent power to interpret the Equal Protection Clause but because the tiers of scrutiny are rules that guide judicial decisionmaking and need not apply to Congressional determinations of invidiousness.
That takes us a significant way towards the popular constitutionalist results, but it does so while maintaining judicial supremacy in constitutional interpretation, something that Larry Sager recognized in the article I mentioned last time. (It is, in fact, the approach the Supreme Court used to take, until it turned away in City of
But here an objection might arise: why should the Court care what Congress thinks is invidious? Shouldn’t the question be what the drafters (or, more precisely, the ratifiers) of the 14th Amendment thought was invidious?
This is a useful objection because it brings up the second theoretical topic: originalism vs. the living constitution. This is one of the standard debates of constitutional theory: should judges be able to change the meaning of the Constitution to adapt it to the changing needs of society, or should constitutional change be reserved to the article V amendment process and the Constitution enforced according to the original understanding of its terms?
The debate is a standard, but I think it is quite overblown. As Jack Balkin has recently suggested on this blog, there’s a difference between the meaning of a constitutional provision and its range of application. (A comment on that post suggested that this is similar to Gottlob Frege’s distinction between sense and reference, which I think is actually quite a good way of putting it for those with a background in analytic philosophy.) That is, a constitutional provision saying that the President must have attained 35 years of age will make some people eligible in 1789 and other people eligible in 2000. A provision directing Senators to dress in “the latest fashions” (that one doesn’t exist) would direct one style of dress when ratified and another one now. Or more generally: if the application of a constitutional provision depends on current circumstances, the outcomes of cases under that provision will change as time passes without any sort of change in its meaning. With provisions like that, we can follow the original understanding while not reaching the same results that the ratifiers would have
The big question, of course, is which constitutional provisions are of that sort. The one the Court has identified most explicitly is the 8th Amendment’s cruel and unusual punishment clause, which, it has said, reflects the evolving standards of decency that mark the progress of a civilized society. Originalists tend to think that we should be asking instead what was considered cruel and unusual in 1789. But anyone writing a constitution intended to endure for the ages would be unlikely to intend that approach. It will give you a set of prohibitions almost certain to lose fit with societal understandings. Either society will get more sensitive—no one would think of drawing and quartering anymore—and the 8th amendment will become irrelevant; or it will become less sensitive—we’ll come to see that drawing and quartering really isn’t so bad—and the amendment will start to seem an annoying and pointless restriction. Neither of these alternatives makes a lot of sense. And it’s worth noting that when the constitution writers did think that highly specific practices were so bad that they should not be allowed, they’ve been able to list them—no ex post facto laws, no bills of attainder, no quartering of troops in houses in peacetime. No slavery. No alcohol—that one didn’t really stand the test of time, but it’s certainly specific. Cruel and unusual punishment doesn’t sound like those.
But that’s a relatively minor example. The Equal Protection Clause is a bigger one. As I’ve mentioned already, the Supreme Court has repeatedly said that the meaning of the Equal Protection Clause is that states can’t discriminate invidiously. They can’t treat people differently without a legitimate reason. An originalist would say that in order to figure out what the equal protection clause prohibits, we need to ask what the drafters and ratifiers thought it prohibited. What did they think was invidious discrimination? What did they think was a legitimate reason for differential treatment?
Let’s consider a couple of answers to these questions. The drafters almost certainly did not think that the equal protection clause prohibited segregated schools. The same congress that drafted the equal protection clause was running a segregated school system. They almost certainly did not think it prohibited bans on interracial marriage. And they almost certainly did not think it required states to allow women to practice law, or pursue most professions.
The more interesting question is why they thought that these forms of discrimination were not invidious. For segregated schools, the answer probably has two components. One, they thought that blacks and whites were different enough that integrated schools were simply impossible. Two, relatedly, they thought that segregation was not stigmatizing or intended to promote notions of racial superiority—and if integration is just impossible, this is perhaps plausible. For marriage, they had available a substantial body of scientific literature telling them that interracial unions would produce monsters. And for excluding women from the practice of law, as Justice Bradley put it, concurring in a decision that allowed Illinois to do just that, they had the rationale that, “the natural timidity and delicacy of the female evidently unfits her for many of the occupations of civil life.” So what are women to do? Well, Bradley went on to explain that “[t]he paramount destiny and mission of woman are to fulfill the noble and benign offices of wife and mother. This is the law of the Creator.”
None of the rationales I’ve just listed is something that’s within the mainstream of public opinion today. None of them looks legitimate. If someone tried to defend discrimination on these grounds, the response would be that he’s racist, or sexist, or just plain crazy. So what is the Supreme Court to do? Originalism seems to suggest that it should enforce these understandings anyway: it should say, sorry, this is what the Constitution means, and although these attitudes may seem reprehensible or factually wrong, fidelity to the Constitution requires us to continue to apply them. There is an opinion that takes much this approach, but it is not one that the Court relies on much nowadays. It is Dred Scott, where Taney invoked the supposed racism of the Framers to conclude that blacks could never be citizens entitled to invoke diversity jurisdiction.
But the argument against this approach is not just guilt by association. If you think about what the ratifiers would have expected to happen to value-laden provisions like the Equal Protection Clause over the course of time, I think it’s much more likely that they would expect future understandings of invidiousness to govern. If the equal protection clause prohibits only what its drafters thought at the time was invidious, it will rapidly become either irrelevant or unduly constraining, like a time-bound 8th Amendment. It would be a more sensible constitutional provision if it let subsequent generations come to their own conclusions about what is invidious. This is, of course, a supposition that historical research might defeat, but I have never seen a defense of originalism that attempts to do so, and the scholarship I have seen, like Jeff Powell’s The Original Understanding of Original Intent, tends to support it.
The distinction that I have relied on so far is basically the distinction between the meaning of a constitutional provision and the range of its application. Jack pointed out that we can adhere to the original meaning, or original understanding, while not retaining the same range of application. I add the suggestion that this interpretive approach might very well be what the ratifiers expected would happen. This is not quite the same thing as the distinction between meaning and doctrine. That distinction comes in at a later stage in the argument, in order to explain how doctrine can change—the level of scrutiny applied to sex discrimination can increase, for instance—without the meaning of the Constitution changing. Once it decides that sex discrimination tends to be invidious, that is, the Court can change its doctrine in response without altering constitutional meaning. The general point is the same: the outcome of cases can change, and the doctrinal rules the Court applies can change, without there being any change in the meaning of the Constitution. Thus, originalism and the living constitution are not in fact the mutually exclusive alternatives that people tend to suppose.
That concludes the preview of the theory part of the book. If you’re still reading, thanks—I’m not doing a great job of keeping this short, and I have some worries about how accessible it is, though I think that this blog has a pretty technically sophisticated readership. Tomorrow I will put together the perspectives of this post and the previous one and take a look at some cases.
A problem I see here, is that about the time the Court was starting to consider whether sex discrimination was invidious, a constutional amendment was drafted, and submitted to the states, to make exactly that determination.
ReplyDeleteIt was rejected.
So, in essence, what the Court has done, is to ratify an amendment that the states refused to ratify. That's not circumventing Article V, that's negating it.
Obat sipilis atau raja singa
ReplyDeleteObat sipilis herbal
Obat sipilis murah
Obat sipilis manjur
Obat sipilis antibiotik
Obat sipilis adalah
Obat sipilis generik
Obat sipilis ampuh
Obat sipilis atau raja singa
Obat sipilis herbal
Obat sipilis murah
Obat sipilis jogja
Obat sipilis Yang manjur
obat sipilis denature indonesia
Obat sipilis resep dokter
Obat sipilis paling manjur
Obat sipilis pada wanita
Obat sipilis paling ampuh
Obat sipilis manjur
Obat sipilis ampuh
Obat sipilis atau raja singa
Obat sipilis herbal
Obat sipilis murah
Obat sipilis ampuh
Obat sipilis atau raja singa
Obat sipilis herbal
Obat sipilis murah
Obat sipilis jogja
Obat sipilis apotik
Obat sipilis apa ya
Obat sipilis akut
Obat sipilis amoxilin
ramuan obat herpes tradisional
ReplyDeleteresep obat herpes
ramuan obat herpes
obat herpes kulit ringan
obat herpes selain acyclovir
obat herpes salep acyclovir
obat herpes secara alami
obat herpes sembuh total
obat herpes selangkangan
Obat kutil kelamin/jengger ayam
Obat kutil kelamin paling murah
Obat kutil kelamin dari dalam
Obat antibiotik kutil kelamin
Obat kutil kelamin yang dijual di apotik
Beli obat kutil kelamin di apotik
Nama obat kutil kelamin di apotek
Obat kutil kelamin yang tersedia di apotik
Cuka apel obat kutil kelamin
Obat ampuh menghilangkan kutil kelamin
Obat alami menyembuhkan kutil kelamin
Obat apotek untuk kutil kelamin
Apa obat untuk kutil kelamin
Obat alami untuk mengobati kutil kelamin
Obat kutil kelamin yang ada di apotik
Obat kutil kelamin bandung
Beli obat kutil kelamin
Dimana beli obat kutil kelamin
Obat tradisional buat kutil kelamin
ReplyDeleteObat salep buat kutil kelamin
Www.obat kutil kelamin.com
Obat cina kutil kelamin
Cuka obat kutil kelamin
Obat cina untuk kutil kelamin
obat herpes secara tradisional
obat herpes soster
obat herpes selain asiklovir
obat herpes simplex untuk ibu hamil
obat herpes simplex pada anak
obat herpes simplex adalah
obat sakit herpes kulit
obat salep herpes zoster
obat salep herpes kelamin
obat herpes tradisional
Obat kutil kelamin yang untuk wanita hamil
obat kutil di sekitar kelamin
obat sakit kutil kelamin
obat kutil kelamin terbaik
obat kutil kelamin salep
obat kutil kelamin terbaru
obat tradisional kutil kelamin
obat tradisional untuk kutil kelamin
obat herbal untuk kutil kelamin
obat tradisional untuk menyembuhkan kutil kelamin
obat kutil kelamin yang tersedia di apotek
Obat wasir alami yang ampuh
ReplyDeleteObat wasir anoral
Obat wasir ambeven
Obat wasir ardium hd
Obat wasir berdarah di apotik
Obat wasir bentuk peluru
Obat wasir bengkak
Obat wasir boraginol
Obat wasir bagus
Obat wasir paling ampuh
Obat wasir ardium
Obat wasir di apotik
Obat wasir luar
Obat wasir ampuh di apotik
Obat wasir alami dari tumbuhan
Obat wasir untuk ibu menyusui
Obat wasir parah
Obat wasir venaron
Obat wasir dalam
Obat wasir alami bagus
Obat wasir ampuh tanpa operasi
Obat wasir ambeien
Obat wasir ambeclear
Obat wasir akut
Obat wasir atau ambeien
Obat wasir aman untuk ibu hamil
Obat wasir ampuh bagus
Obat wasir alami untuk ibu hamil
Obat wasir anak
Cuka apel obat kutil kelamin
Obat ampuh menghilangkan kutil kelamin
Obat alami menyembuhkan kutil kelamin
Obat apotek untuk kutil kelamin
Apa obat untuk kutil kelamin
Obat sipilis Obat kutil kelamin obat wasir
ReplyDeleteObat sipilis raja singa paling ampuh
obat sipilis amoxicillin
obat sipilis adalah
obat sipilis atau raja singa
obat sipilis apa
obat sipilis anjuran dokter
obat sipilis apa ya
obat sifilis akut
obat sipilis apa namanya
obat alami sipilis pada pria
obat antibiotik sipilis di apotik
obat sifilis ampuh
apa obat sipilis
obat sifilis apotek
obat sifilis adalah
obat sifilis atau raja singa
Cara paling ampuh mengobati kutil kelamin
pengobatan ampuh kutil kelamin pada wanita
obat kutil kelamin yang ada di apotik
obat kutil kelamin yg dijual di apotik
obat kutil di kemaluan wanita
pengobatan kutil kelamin pada pria
pengobatan penyakit kutil kelamin pada pria
obat penyakit kutil pada kelamin pria
Pengobatan kutil kelamin aman dan tanpa operasi
obat kutil pada alat kelamin pria
pengobatan kutil kelamin
Obat herpes zoster tradisional
Obat herpes untuk ibu hamil
Obat herpes ampuh
Obat herpes untuk anak
Obat herpes mulut
Obat herpes tradisional yang ampuh
Obat herpes untuk balita
ReplyDeleteObat herpes selain acyclovir
Obat herpes di wajah
Obat herpes alami
Obat herpes di leher
Obat salep buat kutil kelamin
Obat cina kutil kelamin
Cuka obat kutil kelamin
Obat cina untuk kutil kelamin
Obat cina penghilang kutil kelamin
Obat china untuk kutil kelamin
Obat kutil di kelamin pria
Obat tradisional kutil di kelamin
Obat kutil di daerah kelamin
Obat untuk menghilangkan kutil di kelamin
Obat sipilis
Obat sipilis Yang manjur
obat sipilis denature indonesia
Obat sipilis resep dokter
Obat sipilis paling manjur
Obat sipilis pada wanita
Obat sipilis paling ampuh
Obat sipilis manjur
Obat sipilis ampuh
Obat sipilis atau raja singa
Obat sipilis herbal
Obat sipilis murah
Obat sipilis anjuran dokter
Obat sipilis apa namanya
Obat sipilis dijual di apotik
Obat alami sipilis pada pria
Obat sifilis ampuh
Obat sipilis buat wanita
Obat sipilis bagi wanita
Obat buat sipilis